📊Order Theory Unit 6 – Completeness and continuity

Completeness and continuity are fundamental concepts in order theory, focusing on the existence of certain elements in partially ordered sets and the preservation of order structures by functions. These ideas are crucial for understanding fixed points, suprema, and infima in various mathematical structures. The study of completeness and continuity has wide-ranging applications in mathematics and computer science. From domain theory in programming language semantics to topology and optimization, these concepts provide powerful tools for analyzing ordered structures and their transformations.

Key Concepts and Definitions

  • Order theory studies partially ordered sets (posets) and their properties
  • A poset (P,)(P, \leq) consists of a set PP and a binary relation \leq that is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive
  • An upper bound of a subset SS of a poset PP is an element uPu \in P such that sus \leq u for all sSs \in S
  • A least upper bound (lub) or supremum of a subset SS is an upper bound uu such that uvu \leq v for any other upper bound vv of SS
    • Denoted as supS\sup S or S\vee S
  • A lower bound and greatest lower bound (glb) or infimum are defined dually
    • Denoted as infS\inf S or S\wedge S
  • A lattice is a poset in which every pair of elements has a lub and a glb
  • A complete lattice is a poset in which every subset has a lub and a glb

Completeness in Ordered Sets

  • Completeness is a fundamental property in order theory that ensures the existence of certain elements in a poset
  • A poset is complete if every subset has a least upper bound and a greatest lower bound
  • In a complete poset, every directed subset (a non-empty subset where any two elements have an upper bound in the subset) has a supremum
  • Completeness allows for the construction of fixed points and the application of the Knaster-Tarski theorem
    • The Knaster-Tarski theorem states that every order-preserving function on a complete lattice has a fixed point
  • Complete lattices have many desirable properties, such as the existence of a top element (greatest element) and a bottom element (least element)
  • Examples of complete lattices include the real numbers with the usual order, the power set of a set ordered by inclusion, and the set of all functions from a set to a complete lattice

Types of Completeness

  • Chain-completeness: A poset is chain-complete if every chain (a totally ordered subset) has a supremum
    • Every complete poset is chain-complete, but the converse is not true
  • Conditional completeness: A poset is conditionally complete if every bounded subset has a supremum and an infimum
    • Bounded means there exists an upper and lower bound for the subset
  • Dedekind-completeness: A linearly ordered set is Dedekind-complete if every non-empty subset that is bounded above has a supremum
    • The real numbers are Dedekind-complete, while the rational numbers are not
  • σ\sigma-completeness: A poset is σ\sigma-complete if every countable subset has a supremum and an infimum
    • Every complete poset is σ\sigma-complete, but the converse is not true
  • Directed-completeness: A poset is directed-complete if every directed subset has a supremum
    • Every complete poset is directed-complete, but the converse is not true

Continuity in Order Theory

  • Continuity in order theory is a property of functions between posets that preserves certain order-theoretic structures
  • A function f:PQf: P \to Q between posets is order-preserving or monotone if xyx \leq y in PP implies f(x)f(y)f(x) \leq f(y) in QQ
  • An order-preserving function f:PQf: P \to Q is called residuated if for every yQy \in Q, the set {xP:f(x)y}\{x \in P : f(x) \leq y\} has a greatest element
    • The greatest element is denoted as f(y)f^\sharp(y) and the function f:QPf^\sharp: Q \to P is called the residual of ff
  • A function f:PQf: P \to Q between complete lattices is join-continuous if f(S)=f(S)f(\vee S) = \vee f(S) for every subset SS of PP
    • Meet-continuity is defined dually
  • Scott-continuity is a stronger notion of continuity for functions between complete lattices
    • A function f:PQf: P \to Q is Scott-continuous if it is order-preserving and preserves directed suprema, i.e., f(D)=f(D)f(\vee D) = \vee f(D) for every directed subset DD of PP

Relationships Between Completeness and Continuity

  • Completeness and continuity are closely related concepts in order theory
  • The Knaster-Tarski theorem connects completeness and fixed points of order-preserving functions
    • Every order-preserving function on a complete lattice has a fixed point
  • The Kleene fixed-point theorem relates Scott-continuity and least fixed points
    • Every Scott-continuous function on a complete lattice has a least fixed point, which is the supremum of the iterates of the function starting from the bottom element
  • Continuity is preserved under composition and pointwise suprema
    • If f:PQf: P \to Q and g:QRg: Q \to R are continuous functions between complete lattices, then their composition gf:PRg \circ f: P \to R is also continuous
    • If (fi)iI(f_i)_{i \in I} is a family of continuous functions from PP to QQ, then the pointwise supremum iIfi\vee_{i \in I} f_i is also continuous
  • Adjunctions between complete lattices correspond to pairs of order-preserving functions that satisfy a certain continuity condition
    • If f:PQf: P \to Q and g:QPg: Q \to P are order-preserving functions such that xg(y)f(x)yx \leq g(y) \Leftrightarrow f(x) \leq y for all xPx \in P and yQy \in Q, then ff is join-continuous and gg is meet-continuous

Applications and Examples

  • Completeness and continuity have numerous applications in various fields of mathematics and computer science
  • In domain theory, complete lattices and continuous functions are used to model the semantics of programming languages and to study the properties of recursive definitions
    • The Scott domain is a complete lattice used to interpret lambda calculus and programming language semantics
  • In topology, complete lattices and continuous functions are used to study the properties of open and closed sets, as well as to define the Scott topology on a poset
  • In algebra, complete lattices and residuated functions are used to study the properties of ideals and filters in rings and modules
  • In analysis, the Dedekind-completeness of the real numbers is a fundamental property that distinguishes them from the rational numbers and allows for the development of calculus and real analysis
  • In optimization theory, complete lattices and continuous functions are used to study the existence and properties of optimal solutions to optimization problems
    • The Knaster-Tarski theorem can be used to prove the existence of Nash equilibria in game theory

Theorems and Proofs

  • The Knaster-Tarski theorem: Every order-preserving function f:PPf: P \to P on a complete lattice PP has a fixed point
    • Proof sketch: Consider the set S={xP:f(x)x}S = \{x \in P : f(x) \leq x\}. SS is non-empty (since PP has a top element) and closed under infima (since ff is order-preserving). Let x=infSx^* = \inf S. Then f(x)xf(x^*) \leq x^* (since xSx^* \in S) and xf(x)x^* \leq f(x^*) (since xx^* is a lower bound of SS). Thus, f(x)=xf(x^*) = x^*.
  • The Kleene fixed-point theorem: Every Scott-continuous function f:PPf: P \to P on a complete lattice PP has a least fixed point, which is given by nNfn()\vee_{n \in \mathbb{N}} f^n(\bot), where \bot is the bottom element of PP and fnf^n denotes the nn-fold composition of ff with itself
    • Proof sketch: Let x=nNfn()x^* = \vee_{n \in \mathbb{N}} f^n(\bot). Since ff is Scott-continuous, f(x)=f(nNfn())=nNfn+1()=xf(x^*) = f(\vee_{n \in \mathbb{N}} f^n(\bot)) = \vee_{n \in \mathbb{N}} f^{n+1}(\bot) = x^*. Thus, xx^* is a fixed point of ff. If yy is another fixed point of ff, then y\bot \leq y and fn()fn(y)=yf^n(\bot) \leq f^n(y) = y for all nNn \in \mathbb{N}, so xyx^* \leq y.
  • The Adjunction Theorem: Let PP and QQ be complete lattices. If f:PQf: P \to Q and g:QPg: Q \to P are order-preserving functions such that xg(y)f(x)yx \leq g(y) \Leftrightarrow f(x) \leq y for all xPx \in P and yQy \in Q, then ff is join-continuous and gg is meet-continuous
    • Proof sketch: Let SPS \subseteq P. Then f(S)ySg(y)sS:sg(y)sS:f(s)yf(S)yf(\vee S) \leq y \Leftrightarrow \vee S \leq g(y) \Leftrightarrow \forall s \in S: s \leq g(y) \Leftrightarrow \forall s \in S: f(s) \leq y \Leftrightarrow \vee f(S) \leq y. Thus, f(S)=f(S)f(\vee S) = \vee f(S). The proof for gg is dual.

Exercises and Problem-Solving Strategies

  • When proving that a poset is complete, try to show that every subset has a supremum and an infimum
    • For suprema, show that the set of upper bounds is non-empty and closed under infima
    • For infima, show that the set of lower bounds is non-empty and closed under suprema
  • When proving that a function is continuous, try to show that it preserves the relevant order-theoretic structures
    • For order-preserving functions, show that xyx \leq y implies f(x)f(y)f(x) \leq f(y)
    • For join-continuous functions, show that f(S)=f(S)f(\vee S) = \vee f(S) for every subset SS
    • For Scott-continuous functions, show that ff is order-preserving and f(D)=f(D)f(\vee D) = \vee f(D) for every directed subset DD
  • When solving problems involving fixed points, try to apply the relevant fixed-point theorems
    • For order-preserving functions on complete lattices, use the Knaster-Tarski theorem
    • For Scott-continuous functions on complete lattices, use the Kleene fixed-point theorem
  • When solving problems involving adjunctions, try to establish the adjunction condition xg(y)f(x)yx \leq g(y) \Leftrightarrow f(x) \leq y and use the Adjunction Theorem to deduce the continuity of ff and gg
  • When solving problems involving the relationship between completeness and continuity, try to use the properties of complete lattices and continuous functions to establish the desired result
    • For example, to prove that a function has a fixed point, show that its domain is a complete lattice and that the function is order-preserving or Scott-continuous


© 2024 Fiveable Inc. All rights reserved.
AP® and SAT® are trademarks registered by the College Board, which is not affiliated with, and does not endorse this website.

© 2024 Fiveable Inc. All rights reserved.
AP® and SAT® are trademarks registered by the College Board, which is not affiliated with, and does not endorse this website.