All Study Guides Intro to Epistemology Unit 4
🤓 Intro to Epistemology Unit 4 – Knowledge Analysis: Tripartite & GettierKnowledge analysis explores the nature of knowledge, focusing on the tripartite theory and Gettier problems. The tripartite theory defines knowledge as justified true belief, while Gettier challenges its sufficiency through counterexamples.
This unit examines alternative theories like reliabilism and causal theories, which attempt to address Gettier's concerns. It also explores the implications of these debates for science, law, politics, and education.
Key Concepts
Epistemology studies the nature, sources, and limits of knowledge
Knowledge is a justified true belief (JTB) according to the tripartite theory
Gettier problems challenge the sufficiency of JTB for knowledge
Epistemic luck occurs when a belief is true by chance rather than justification
Reliabilism holds that a belief is justified if it is produced by a reliable process
Causal theories argue that knowledge requires a causal connection between belief and fact
Virtue epistemology emphasizes the role of intellectual virtues in acquiring knowledge
Historical Context
Epistemology has been a central concern in Western philosophy since ancient Greece
Plato's Theaetetus is an early exploration of the nature of knowledge
Descartes' Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) sought to establish a foundation for knowledge
Locke's An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689) developed an empiricist theory of knowledge
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781) examined the limits of reason and the conditions for knowledge
20th-century developments include logical positivism, ordinary language philosophy, and naturalized epistemology
The Tripartite Theory of Knowledge
The tripartite theory defines knowledge as justified true belief (JTB)
A belief is an attitude or mental state of accepting a proposition as true
Truth is a necessary condition for knowledge; false beliefs cannot constitute knowledge
Justification is the reason or evidence that supports the belief
Justification must be sufficient to warrant the belief
Justification must be internally accessible to the knower
The JTB theory was widely accepted until challenged by Gettier problems in 1963
Gettier Problems
Edmund Gettier (1963) presented counterexamples to the JTB theory
In Gettier cases, a belief is true and justified but does not seem to count as knowledge
Example: Smith believes Jones will get the job and has 10 coins in his pocket
Smith's belief is justified based on strong evidence
Unknown to Smith, he himself will get the job and coincidentally has 10 coins in his pocket
Smith's belief is true and justified but only by luck, not knowledge
Gettier problems show that JTB is not sufficient for knowledge
Responses to Gettier include adding a fourth condition or denying that Gettier cases are possible
Criticisms and Debates
The Gettier problem has generated extensive debate in epistemology
Some argue that Gettier cases rely on questionable intuitions about knowledge
Others defend the JTB theory by denying that Gettier cases are genuine counterexamples
Infallibilism holds that knowledge requires absolute certainty and immunity from error
Infallibilism avoids Gettier problems but sets a very high standard for knowledge
Fallibilism allows for knowledge even in the face of possible error
Fallibilism is more plausible but must contend with Gettier-style challenges
The lottery problem raises questions about the consistency of our knowledge attributions
Alternative Theories
Reliabilism defines justification in terms of reliable belief-forming processes
A belief is justified if it is produced by a process that reliably leads to true beliefs
Reliabilism avoids Gettier problems by requiring a tight connection between belief and truth
Causal theories require a causal connection between the fact that makes a belief true and the belief itself
Knowledge is "caused by the truth" rather than merely coinciding with it
Virtue epistemology shifts the focus from beliefs to the intellectual character of the knower
Intellectual virtues like open-mindedness and diligence are key to acquiring knowledge
Contextualism holds that the standards for knowledge vary by context
In some contexts (e.g., everyday life), the standards for knowledge are relatively low
In other contexts (e.g., philosophical skepticism), the standards are much higher
Real-World Applications
Epistemology has important implications for many areas of life
In science, epistemology informs our understanding of the scientific method and the reliability of scientific knowledge
In law, epistemological issues arise in assessing witness testimony and the burden of proof
In politics, epistemology is relevant to questions of media literacy and the spread of misinformation
In education, epistemology shapes our views on the nature and goals of learning
Epistemological debates also have practical consequences for issues like skepticism and relativism
Key Thinkers and Readings
Plato (Theaetetus)
René Descartes (Meditations on First Philosophy)
John Locke (An Essay Concerning Human Understanding)
Immanuel Kant (Critique of Pure Reason)
Edmund Gettier ("Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?")
Alvin Goldman (Epistemology and Cognition)
Linda Zagzebski (Virtues of the Mind)
Duncan Pritchard (Epistemic Luck)