🔠Intro to Semantics and Pragmatics Unit 8 – Implicature and Presupposition

Implicature and presupposition are key concepts in pragmatics, exploring how we convey and interpret meaning beyond literal words. Implicature deals with implied meanings, while presupposition involves unstated assumptions speakers make when communicating. These concepts rely on shared knowledge and context, allowing efficient communication. Grice's Cooperative Principle and maxims provide a framework for understanding implicature, while various triggers and accommodation explain presupposition phenomena in language use.

Key Concepts

  • Implicature conveys additional meaning beyond literal semantic content of utterances
  • Presupposition refers to implicit assumptions speakers make when producing utterances
  • Grice's Cooperative Principle outlines four maxims (quantity, quality, relation, manner) governing conversation
  • Conventional implicature derives from specific words or phrases (but, even, too)
  • Conversational implicature arises from contextual factors and can be particularized or generalized
  • Presupposition triggers include definite descriptions, factive verbs, change of state verbs, iteratives, and cleft constructions
  • Accommodation allows listeners to accept presuppositions not previously part of common ground
  • Presupposition projection explains how presuppositions of complex sentences relate to those of component clauses

Defining Implicature and Presupposition

  • Implicature refers to implied meaning not directly stated in utterances
  • Presupposition involves unstated assumptions speakers make when producing utterances
  • Implicature and presupposition rely on shared knowledge and context for interpretation
  • Grice distinguishes between "what is said" (semantics) and "what is implicated" (pragmatics)
  • Presuppositions typically survive negation and questioning of containing utterances (The King of France is not bald still presupposes France has a king)
  • Implicatures are cancellable without contradiction while presuppositions are not (I ate some of the cookies implicates not eating all, but this can be cancelled: In fact, I ate all of them)
  • Both implicature and presupposition contribute to efficient communication by allowing speakers to convey information without stating it explicitly

Types of Implicature

  • Conventional implicature derives from meaning of specific words (but, even, too)
    • "Even John passed the test" implicates John was unlikely to pass
    • "Mary is poor but honest" implicates an unexpected contrast between poverty and honesty
  • Conversational implicature depends on context and Gricean maxims
    • Generalized conversational implicatures arise in absence of special circumstances (Some implicates not all)
    • Particularized conversational implicatures require specific contextual factors (Saying "The weather is nice" to a host may implicate "Let's go outside")
  • Scalar implicature is a type of generalized conversational implicature involving scales (some/all, might/must)
    • "Some students passed" implicates not all students passed due to the maxim of quantity
  • Relevance implicature arises when an utterance flouts the maxim of relation
    • Responding "I have to study" when asked to go out implicates refusing the invitation

Types of Presupposition

  • Existential presuppositions assume existence of referents (The King of France presupposes France has a king)
  • Factive presuppositions arise from factive verbs (know, regret, realize)
    • "John regrets smoking" presupposes John smoked
  • Lexical presuppositions are triggered by specific words (stop, start, continue)
    • "John stopped smoking" presupposes John previously smoked
  • Structural presuppositions result from certain syntactic structures (clefts, wh-questions)
    • "It was John who broke the vase" presupposes someone broke the vase
  • Non-factive presuppositions involve verbs like dream, imagine, pretend
    • "Mary dreamed she won the lottery" does not presuppose Mary won the lottery
  • Counterfactual presuppositions arise from counterfactual conditionals
    • "If I were rich, I would travel more" presupposes I am not rich

Theoretical Frameworks

  • Grice's Cooperative Principle and conversational maxims (quantity, quality, relation, manner) provide foundation for implicature
  • Neo-Gricean approaches (Horn, Levinson) reformulate Grice's maxims
    • Horn's Q and R principles relate to quantity and relevance
    • Levinson's Q, I, and M heuristics correspond to quantity, informativeness, and manner
  • Relevance Theory (Sperber and Wilson) treats relevance as key factor in implicature derivation
    • Utterances raise expectations of relevance warranting processing effort
  • Dynamic Semantics views meaning as potential to change context
    • Presuppositions are treated as requirements on input contexts
  • Discourse Representation Theory (Kamp) uses discourse representation structures to model presupposition and accommodation
  • Accommodation (Lewis) explains how presuppositions not already accepted become part of common ground

Real-World Applications

  • Advertising often uses implicature to suggest product benefits without explicitly stating them
    • "The world's most popular soft drink" implicates high quality and desirability
  • Political speech relies on implicature to convey messages while maintaining deniability
    • "My opponent has no experience in foreign policy" implicates the opponent is unqualified without directly stating it
  • Presupposition can be used to manipulate discourse and influence opinions
    • Asking "When did you stop beating your wife?" presupposes the addressee has beaten their wife
  • Understanding implicature and presupposition is crucial for successful cross-cultural communication
    • Different cultures may have different norms for what is implicated or presupposed in conversation
  • Analyzing implicature and presupposition can provide insight into speaker beliefs and attitudes
    • Presupposing something as fact can reveal a speaker's biases or assumptions
  • Natural language processing systems must account for implicature and presupposition to correctly interpret user input
    • A search for "cheap hotels in Paris" presupposes the existence of hotels in Paris and implicates the user's price preferences

Common Challenges and Misconceptions

  • Implicatures can be difficult to identify and interpret, especially across cultures or in written communication lacking nonverbal cues
  • Presuppositions are not always easy to distinguish from entailments or logical implications
    • "John's brother is bald" entails John has a brother, while "John's dog is cute" presupposes John has a dog
  • Presupposition projection in complex sentences can lead to confusion
    • "If John has a sister, his sister is blonde" does not presuppose John has a sister, despite "John's sister" typically triggering this presupposition
  • The line between semantics and pragmatics is not always clear, leading to debate over the nature of implicature and presupposition
  • Some argue that implicature and presupposition should be explained in purely pragmatic terms, while others maintain they have a semantic component
  • Accommodation is not always straightforward, and listeners may sometimes fail to accommodate presuppositions, leading to misunderstanding
  • The Cooperative Principle and conversational maxims are not always followed in real-world conversation, complicating implicature derivation

Further Reading and Resources

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 3: Speech Acts (pp. 41-58). New York: Academic Press.
  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Horn, L. R. (1984). Toward a new taxonomy for pragmatic inference: Q-based and R-based implicature. In D. Schiffrin (Ed.), Meaning, Form, and Use in Context: Linguistic Applications (pp. 11-42). Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Karttunen, L. (1973). Presuppositions of compound sentences. Linguistic Inquiry, 4(2), 169-193.
  • Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal Methods in the Study of Language (pp. 277-322). Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts.
  • Beaver, D. I., & Geurts, B. (2014). Presupposition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/presupposition/
  • Potts, C. (2015). Presupposition and implicature. In S. Lappin & C. Fox (Eds.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (2nd ed., pp. 168-202). Wiley-Blackwell.


© 2024 Fiveable Inc. All rights reserved.
AP® and SAT® are trademarks registered by the College Board, which is not affiliated with, and does not endorse this website.

© 2024 Fiveable Inc. All rights reserved.
AP® and SAT® are trademarks registered by the College Board, which is not affiliated with, and does not endorse this website.